Filters
Question type

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -In Midgley's view, we may need to praise things which we do not fully understand.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

True

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -According to Midgley, we can come to see other societies better by:


A) making their questions our own.
B) recognizing that their questions are really forms of the questions which we are asking already.
C) both a and b.
D) neither a nor b.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley notes that nearly all cultures are the product of a number of different influences. Does this claim call into question moral isolationism? Even if a moral isolationist grants this claim, might she still maintain her position?

Correct Answer

Answered by ExamLex AI

Answered by ExamLex AI

Yes, Midgley's claim that nearly all cul...

View Answer

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley claims that moral skepticism could lead only to our losing all interest in moral questions, most of all in those which concern other societies.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley holds that we are rightly angry with those who:


A) despise other cultures.
B) oppress other cultures.
C) steamroll other cultures.
D) all of the above.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley defines "moral isolationism" as the view that:


A) denies that we can ever understand any culture except our own well enough to make judgments about it.
B) respect and tolerance forbids us ever to take up a critical position to any other culture.
C) moral judgment is a kind of coinage valid only in its country of origin.
D) all of the above.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley maintains that moral isolationism would lay down a general ban on:


A) moral reasoning.
B) moral communication.
C) moral disagreement.
D) moral agreement.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -According to Midgley, we could not condemn insolence if we thought that:


A) our condemnations were just quirks of our own culture.
B) Nietzsche was right.
C) non-cognitivists were right.
D) none of the above.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley holds that "judging" means:


A) sentencing people.
B) forming an opinion.
C) condemning people.
D) praising people.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

B

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley claims that when we judge something to be bad or good, better or worse than something else:


A) we are taking it as something to promote or preserve.
B) we are taking it as an example to aim at or avoid.
C) we are making a moral mistake.
D) our statements are meaningless.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley claims that nobody can respect what is entirely unintelligible to them.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -According to Midgley, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Do you think this claim is correct? Why or why not?

Correct Answer

Answered by ExamLex AI

Answered by ExamLex AI

I believe that Mary Midgley's claim that...

View Answer

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -What, according to Midgley, is moral isolationism? What are the merits of moral isolationism? Do you think a version of this position is immune to Midgley's attacks? Explain your answer.

Correct Answer

Answered by ExamLex AI

Answered by ExamLex AI

Moral isolationism, according to Mary Mi...

View Answer

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -According to Midgley, people normally adopt moral isolationism because they think it is a respectful attitude to other cultures.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -According to Midgley, moral isolationism robs us of the chance of profiting by other people's insights or mistakes.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley asserts that if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. What reasons does she provide to support this assertion? Do you find these reasons plausible? Why or why not?

Correct Answer

Answered by ExamLex AI

Answered by ExamLex AI

Midgley provides several reasons to supp...

View Answer

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley claims that we fully understand our own culture

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley maintains that if we accept something as a serious moral truth about one culture:


A) we cannot refuse to apply it to other cultures as well.
B) we need not apply it to other cultures as well.
C) we may permissibly apply it to other similar cultures.
D) we act impermissibly by apply it to other cultures.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley asserts that moral isolationism flows from apathy.

Correct Answer

verifed

verified

Mary Midgley: Trying Out One's New Sword Midgley argues against a view she calls moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand cultures other than our own well enough to make moral judgments about them. Many people, Midgley notes, accept moral isolationism on grounds of respect and tolerance. But, according to Midgley, not only is this wrong it is entirely wrongheaded. To test moral isolationism, Midgley introduces a custom from ancient Japanese culture. Needing to test if their newly crafted swords could cut through a person in a single blow, samurai would slice wayfarers in half. The moral isolationist is committed to holding that, given our lack of understanding of ancient Japanese culture, respect and tolerance demand we refrain from judging the samurai's testing practices. But this verdict is, Midgley argues, mistaken on a number of fronts. First, to respect people we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. Hence, Midgley maintains, the moral isolationist cannot ground her isolationism on both a lack of understanding and respect. Moreover, understanding occurs gradually; it is not all or nothing. Second, moral isolationism, Midgley claims, would undercut moral reasoning as such. For if we cannot judge other cultures, we cannot judge our own. Other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Our moral reasoning, Midgley maintains, is made possible by looking to the practices of others. Accordingly, moral isolationism leads to a kind of moral mental suicide. Abandoning moral isolationism, however, does not come at a high cost. We already, Midgley notes, try to justify the behavior of those we only barely understand. For example, many people's initial reaction is to try and justify the samurai's behavior. But attempting this kind of justification is an implicit denial of moral isolationism. In addition, nearly every culture is a hodgepodge of different influences, and we nonetheless morally engage with our own culture. In short, Midgley concludes that moral isolationism is untenable and the costs of giving it up are not high. -Midgley claims moral reasoning requires the possibility of judging the practices of other societies. What argument does Midgley supply to justify this claim? Do you find her argument plausible? Defend your answer.

Correct Answer

Answered by ExamLex AI

Answered by ExamLex AI

Midgley supplies several arguments to justify her claim that moral reasoning requires the possibility of judging the practices of other societies. First, she argues that in order to respect people, we have to know enough about them to make a favorable judgment. This means that moral isolationism, which holds that we cannot understand other cultures well enough to make moral judgments about them, is contradictory to the idea of respect. Additionally, Midgley points out that understanding of other cultures occurs gradually and is not an all or nothing situation. Therefore, it is possible to gain enough understanding to make moral judgments about other societies. Furthermore, Midgley claims that moral reasoning is made possible by looking to the practices of other societies. If we cannot judge other cultures, then we cannot judge our own, as other societies provide the range of relevant comparison. Therefore, moral isolationism would undercut moral reasoning as a whole, leading to a kind of moral mental suicide. I find Midgley's argument plausible because it is based on the idea that respect and tolerance do not require us to refrain from making moral judgments about other cultures. Instead, she argues that understanding and judging other cultures is essential for moral reasoning. Additionally, her point about the gradual nature of understanding and the necessity of comparing different societies for moral reasoning to occur makes sense. Overall, Midgley's argument provides a strong case against moral isolationism and supports the idea that moral reasoning requires the possibility of judging the practices of other societies.

Showing 1 - 20 of 30

Related Exams

Show Answer